Paul Dowling Culture Communication & Societies Institute of Education University of London I am contemplating a piece of a wall. It is a piece of the Berlin Wall, in fact (I have a certificate that attests to its authenticity). More about the wall a little later. However, in the year of the tenth anniversary of its destruction, I am reminded of John F. Kennedys famously grammatical faux pas in front of the wall and am inclined to pun. It may not be quite the case that the proudest thing a man or woman can say is ich bin ein bernsteinian, but in the same sense that Michel Foucault (Ive forgotten where) declared that we are all marxists now, all of us in the field of educational studies at the close of the twentieth century inhabit a world that has been profoundly influenced by the thinking of Basil Bernstein. We are all, in some respects, Bernsteinians now. In my preparation, therefore, I generated a list of authors whose texts have exhibited some explicit relationship to Bernsteins work. Contemplating the list, it seemed to me that they might be organised within a two dimensional space. I shall use this organisation to structure my discourse. The first dimension is scaled according to the strength of voice that is given to Bernstein by the author. Where the voice is strong, the author has clearly been profoundly influenced by Bernsteins work in terms of the integrity of the latter. Where the voice is weak, terms may have been recruited, but without allowing Bernsteins own conceptualisations to impose upon their use and development. The second dimension is scaled according to the extent to which the author reproduces (weakly or strongly) Bernsteins conceptual structures or, alternatively, works with them and other theoretical antecedents in the production of new frameworks or, to use Bernsteins own term, new languages of description. We might conveniently refer to this dimension as message. Voice and message are, of course, technical terms in Bernsteins own work, but here they are being used differently. Configuring these dimensions as a cartesian product, we obtain the space that is represented in Figure 1. |
1. I do not propose to derive indicators for the quantification of either dimension; the reference to the interval level is an analogy only. back 2. No contemporary fieldnotes being available, I am reconstructing the dialogue as best I can on the basis of unaided memory. back 3. A finding which I cannot resist associating with Beckers famous description of the careers of marijuana users. back 4. A distinction that, of course, predates Bernstein and so whilst sharpened by, cannot be interpreted as simply the product of his theorising. back 5. In this case, the insulation must have a low value of conductance in order to separate two bodies having high conductance. In this sense, insulation is a negative kind of wall. back 6. It would seem that this is a general rule for punctuation marks. Questions marks, for example, that appear to stand in breach of the rule are not, qua question marks, boundaries. That which follows a question mark may or may not be a question. What is asserted, however, is that it will be another sentence. back 7. Or, in an schooling context, Samuel Wilderspins use of cherry trees in the playground (see Hunter, 1994; Dowling, 1998). back 8. In another context, the purchase of a loaf of bread might become the localised instance of specialised domestic science and would be recontextualised to quite different effect. 9. In Dowling (1998 and elsewhere) I measure strength of classification in respect of content and expression separately, thus generating a two dimensional space. The esoteric and public domains refer to those regions for which content and expression are both strong or weak, respectively. The other two possibilities give rise to the descriptive and expressive domains. 10. See also Power et al (1998). 11. The table refers to the following work: Bernstein (1977); Bourdieu (1977, 1990); Eco (1976, regarding Lotman); Foucault (1980); Freud (1973); Lévi-Strauss (1972); Luria (1976, and regarding Lévy-Bruhl); Piaget (1995); Sohn-Rethel (1973, 1975, 1978); Vygotsky (1978, 1986); Walkerdine (1982). |
|||||||||||||||||||||
1. I do not propose to derive indicators for the quantification of either dimension; the reference to the interval level is an analogy only. back 2. No contemporary fieldnotes being available, I am reconstructing the dialogue as best I can on the basis of unaided memory. back 3. A finding which I cannot resist associating with Beckers famous description of the careers of marijuana users. back 4. A distinction that, of course, predates Bernstein and so whilst sharpened by, cannot be interpreted as simply the product of his theorising. back 5. In this case, the insulation must have a low value of conductance in order to separate two bodies having high conductance. In this sense, insulation is a negative kind of wall. back 6. It would seem that this is a general rule for punctuation marks. Questions marks, for example, that appear to stand in breach of the rule are not, qua question marks, boundaries. That which follows a question mark may or may not be a question. What is asserted, however, is that it will be another sentence. back 7. Or, in an schooling context, Samuel Wilderspins use of cherry trees in the playground (see Hunter, 1994; Dowling, 1998). back 8. In another context, the purchase of a loaf of bread might become the localised instance of specialised domestic science and would be recontextualised to quite different effect. 9. In Dowling (1998 and elsewhere) I measure strength of classification in respect of content and expression separately, thus generating a two dimensional space. The esoteric and public domains refer to those regions for which content and expression are both strong or weak, respectively. The other two possibilities give rise to the descriptive and expressive domains. 10. See also Power et al (1998). 11. The table refers to the following work: Bernstein (1977); Bourdieu (1977, 1990); Eco (1976, regarding Lotman); Foucault (1980); Freud (1973); Lévi-Strauss (1972); Luria (1976, and regarding Lévy-Bruhl); Piaget (1995); Sohn-Rethel (1973, 1975, 1978); Vygotsky (1978, 1986); Walkerdine (1982). |
||||||||||||||||||||||
The modality of relationship authors to Bernsteins work |
||||||||||||||||||||||
I am conceiving of the scaling of voice and message as operating at a level analogous to the interval level of measurement rather than the ordinal form that is suggested by Figure 1. [1] Clearly, voice may be more or less strong or weak and message may be more or less reproductive or productive. The configuration of Figure 1 represents simply a clustering of convenience. In discussing these clusters I follow a Z-shaped course, beginning in the upper right-hand cell so that I can finish with my own response in the lower left.
The vulgarisers Nearly twenty years ago, now, I was breakfasting with a friend at her home when her young son dipped his hand into the pot of jam that had been placed in the centre of the table. "Why are you putting your fingers in the jam?" my friend asked, "Wouldnt it be better to use a knife or a spoon?" [2] "Why dont you just tell him to get his hand out of the pot?" I enquired. "Because Basil Bernstein has told us that we should speak to our children in elaborated code." Well, there is a sense in which her control strategy exhibits a degree of context independence that would be characteristic of an elaborated orientation. Certainly more so than, for example, Get your hand out of there. It might be argued, though, that wouldnt it be better tacitly indexes a more or less locally normalised practice rather than constitutes an appeal to a generalised rationality. Clearly, however, the moralising, we should, in this context, is a misreading of Bernstein. Bernsteins voice is clearly very weakly realised in this parents text. Furthermore, as a fairly recent graduate of a teacher training programme, she appeared to be attempting to implementto reproducea message rather than to construct something new of her own. Vulgarising is, of course, an inevitable consequence of notoriety. It is an interesting and important factor in the circulation of rumour and myth and may have crucial consequences for the career of the author whose work is vulgarised. Because of the lack of any serious engagement with the vulgarised work, it may be very difficult for the originating author to engage with the vulgariser other than by dismissal and this, from their point of view, may be less than ideal. For my purposes, however, vulgarising is the least interesting mode of response because it entails no internal or external development of the work vulgarised. It is sufficient to say (and it is sufficiently well known) that Bernsteins work has, indeed, been widely vulgarised in the three decades of his prominence in the field. I shall move directly on to the second category of response. The disciples I am here referring to authors whose responses to Bernsteins work constitute applications, explorations and developments of that work and that adopt, to a greater or lesser extent, its central organising principles. Many, but by no means all of the authors that I would categorise here have worked directly with Bernstein, often under his supervision. I will mention, here, just two of the many available authors in this category. These have been chosen in order to introduce two of Bernsteins key concepts, classification and framing, both of which will be key objects of discussion under my final category, the heretics. Classification and framing refer, respectively, to the structural and interactional levels of analysis of the social. For the time being, it is sufficient to describe classification as a measure of the extent to which categoriesfor example, curriculum subjectsare structurally distinct. Framing, then, is a measure of the degree to which the transmitter of a message maintains control over the communicative context. Harry Daniels (1988, 1995) was interested in school students recognition of and ability to realise specialised school discourses across school contexts exhibiting variations in classification and framing. On the basis of observation and interview data, Daniels first described each of four moderate learning difficulty schools in terms of the strength of classification and framing characterising each of a number of aspects of school relationships. These aspects included the relationship between the school and that which was outside school (including parents, employers etc), relationships between subjects, between teachers, and in the classroom, between teachers and students in terms of the instructional and regulative discourses. The result was a complex description of each school. However, a cline could be described between the school exhibiting weakest to that exhibiting the strongest classification (C) and framing (F). Moving between mathematics and art classrooms in each school, Daniels showed ten pictures individually to a total of eighty children who were asked: We are in a (Maths/Art) lesson. Your teacher is teaching you about (Maths/Art). What would your teacher like to hear you say about this picture in this lesson? Daniels, 1995; p. 525) The pairs of statements for each child were then shown to two teachers, one from a strong C/F school and another from the weakest C/F school. The teachers were asked: 1. Can you tell the difference between these two statements? (ibid) Sixteen children from the original sample were subsequently asked the same questions as the teachers with reference to statements made by three other children (one judged to be good, one poor and one intermediate at producing distinguishable statements). In summary, Daniels found that the ability of the children to realise the specialised discourses was positively correlated with the strength of classification and framing. All but one of the sixteen children in the second phase of the study judged the statements in the same way as the teachers despite having been selected on the basis of their differential performances in the first phase. It would seem, then, that recognition precedes realisation. [3] This study raises, for me, at least one interesting question. The display of realisation rules by children was evaluated by the teachers. One of these teachers was from a high C/F school, the other from the lowest C/F school. In the case of the first teacher, we might presume that the exemplifying and explicit evaluation of such displays in these terms would be a routine feature of their pedagogic practice. In the case of the second teacher, however, this is unlikely to be the case as such actions are themselves strategies that would tend to produce strong C/F. Indeed, viewed from the perspective of the low C/F pedagogic practice, a request to evaluate students displays in these terms might be interpreted as bizarre or, at least, inappropriate. This is because the research design itself is clearly construed from within the perspective of high C/F; it is not reasonable to ask which statement relates to which context under circumstances in which the contexts are not clearly distinguished. My question, then, is what findings would the research have produced had it exhibited a more balanced design. For example, by avoiding specifying the subject to the students (we are in a maths/art lesson) and by asking teachers to evaluate the responses from the perspective of an undifferentiated pedagogic contextwhat does this response tell you about the student? Bernsteins language has clearly opened up the space for both the original research and for my response and provides a means for the systematic interrogation of the nature and productivity of open and closed pedagogies. [4] The second author that I am considering under this category relates to work carried out at the University of Lisbon under the leadership of Ana Morais (Morais et al 1992, 1994, 1999). I shall refer in particular to a comparative content analysis of science curricula relating to the curricular reforms of 1975 and 1991. In this study, the authors coded each sentence of the curriculum documents in terms of their indication of very strong, strong or weak framing. They provide illustrations for each coding thus: F++ [
] which permits one to call the attention of the student to the multiple types of inanimate bodies, of living things and energy manifestations which are part of the environment and, consequently, to sensitize him/her to the relations between the physical and biological world [
] (Morais et al, 1999; p. 43) In general terms, the authors find that there has been a shift towards stronger framing between 1975 and 1991. They suggest that this seems to be counter-intuitive. However,
if we bear in mind that a given official pedagogic discourse tends to reproduce the dominant principles of society, we can understand the direction of change. In fact, the period which corresponds to the 1975 reform is a period which, in socio-political terms, is characterized, in Portugal, by a period of great changea turning, as a consequence of the 1974 revolution, from a dictatorial to a democratic society. In 1991, the young democracy of 1975 had changed to a more stabilized democratic system where there is higher equilibrium between the several socio-political forces. The change may also translate the disenchantment with the innovative pedagogic principles of the 1960s and 1970s. (ibid; p. 51) Now the first sentence in this statement addresses society at a very high level of analysis, that is, at a level at which dominant principles can usefully be articulated. Here, the dominant principles are couched in terms of socio-political modes: dictatorship; young democracy; stabilised democracy. The implication seems to be that the transition between these three modes is characterised by a shift, firstly, from stronger to weaker framing (dictatorship to young democracy) and secondly from weaker to stronger framing (young democracy to stabilised democracy). Thus official pedagogic discoursein this case, science curriculais construed as a mirror of the socio-political mode in terms of framing. This interpretation is, on the face of it, challenged by the publication of The Plowden Report in 1963 (Central Advisory Council, for Education, 1963) at a time when the United Kingdom might reasonably be described as a stabilised democracy. Nevertheless, the strong statement by Morais et al points to a potentially fertile region for research. Is the modality of socio-political forms adequately given in the strength of framing realised in official documentation? An initial response to this question coming from the direction of Bernsteins own work might suggest that the socio-political form is not exclusively concerned with control, but also with power. This being the case, a measure of the realisation of classification in official documentation might appropriately be undertaken alongside the interest in framing. The final sentence in the above extract suggests the possibility of a degree of upward influence between what Bernstein describes as the pedagogic recontextualising field and the official recontextualising field in the reflection within official documentation of a disenchantment on the part of teachers, teacher educators and so forth. The exploiters Authors in this category give weak voice to Bernsteins work which they recruit and exploit in the production of their own message. I am not, in any sense, evaluating this position negatively. However, insofar as this paper is primarily concerned with Bernsteins voice, a lengthy discussion of work in this category seems inappropriate. This is an important area, however, because Bernsteins own responses to this work have often tended to be forceful which itself illustrates a feature of the activity of the academic field. In terms of my own language, these authors cast a gaze on Bernsteins work from the perspective of the esoteric domains of their own respective discourses subordinating the former to the principles of the latter. There is a degree of inevitability about this recontextualising. However, where the recontextualising discourse is sufficiently distinctive with respect to the recontextualised discourse, the result is likely to be constituted as a misrecognition or even a misrepresentation by disciples of the recontextualised discourse. To the extent that the recontextualisers message hegemonises the field, the situation is clearly disastrous for these disciples. Bernstein and his disciples have clearly recognised this and have, on occasion, made strenuous counter-hegemonic efforts to reclaim the message. In this section I shall simply illustrate three of these responses. The first is a response by William Tyler (1988) to Ronald Kings (1976, 1981) attempt to put Bernsteins early theorising of the school to the empirical test. King notes: Bernsteins theories have been generated independently of original research, and so are explanations of a presumed reality, which has been shown here to be, in part, empirically false. Since the theories do not adequately explain the actual changes that have occurred in schools doubts must be expressed about Bernsteins basically adaptive view of educational change, as a response to presumed changes in homologous, superordinate external structures, including the division of labour and the basis of social solidarity. It also suggests that the real existence of the mediators of change, the educational knowledge codes, is at best doubtful, and that their application to the sociology of the school is hypostatic. (King, 1981; pp 261-3) This is a very strong challenge that appears to strike at the heart of Bernsteins message. Tyler, however, constitutes Bernsteins theory in a form which, he claims, makes it inaccessible to the kind of testing that King applied: Because Bernsteins structuralist interpretation of school organisation is so differently conceived from other theories of the school, it does not lend itself easily to conventional empirical testing. Not only does it reconstitute the elements of a theory of school organisation, it also generates its own methodological principles which make any objective empirical test to some degree self validating. Since the instrumentation of empirical research is an aspect of coding practices, an appropriate choice of a method could produce a very distorting result. The main danger with such structuralist theories therefore is that they are not testable by the usual empiricist methods which deal by definition with surface appearances or phenomena. (Tyler, 1988; pp. 159-60) In particular, Tyler accuses King of falling into this trap: By taking the patterns of correlation as evidence of the existence of the codes, he appears to have missed the whole point of a structuralist approach, that it is not the size of the correlation that matters but its position within a patterned field of such relations. (ibid. p. 162) Tyler claims that by choosing the more appropriate canonical correlation analysis, his own work was highly confirmatory of Bernsteins position. The reclaiming job having been performed by Tyler, Bernstein himself needs only to record it in his own reflection: I did not personally carry out empirical research on the model, but R. King collected data on a range of schools and then tried to interpret his results in terms of the model. He concluded that there was only very weak evidence for the relations expected (King, 1976, 1981). However, Tyler (1988) criticizes severely Kings statistical treatment of the data. (Bernstein, 1996; p. 100) The contrast between tried to interpret and criticizes severely carries the force of the dismissal. It is of passing interest that Bernstein neither carried out himself nor supervised the empirical counter to Kings work (Tyler, 1984). However, where an exploiter engages him on theoretical grounds, Bernsteins own involvement is far more likely. His response to Edwards (1987) recontextualising of elaborated code and questioning of the empirical basis for the work, for example, was published as a paper in the same journal as Edwards original paper and is reprinted in Bernsteins book (1994, 1996). In his response Bernstein clearly positions Edwards as what I have termed an exploiter rather than as a disciple, which is to say as an illegitimate rather than a legitimate critic, thus: I shall propose that Edwardss concept of an elaborated code may suit his narrative but has little place in mine. (Bernstein, 1996; p. 157) Edwards interpretation of Bernsteins concept is corrected by the latters survey of that of his own work which was available to Edwards. [Edwards] states an essential defining feature of elaborated codes as Bernstein himself presents them is that meanings are transmitted in ways which give access to the grounds for accepting them and which are therefore open to being challenged. It remains an unusual classroom in which pupils find opportunities for disturbing a body of knowledge. Edwards gives as his reference for this and other statements Bernstein (1973, 1977, 1982, 1985, 1986). Now there is no mention of any statement about elaborated codes as Edwards defines them in Bernstein 1982, nor in the expanded versions of Bernstein 1987 (Bernstein 1990). However, in Bernstein 1986 (p. 182) We are arguing that elaborated orientations, and even more elaborated codes are the media for thinking the "unthinkable", the "impossible" because the meanings they give rise to go beyond local space, time, context and embed and relate the latter to a transcendental space, time and context. A potential of such meanings is disorder, incoherence, a new order, a new coherence. Thus disturbance is a potential of such meanings, not a necessary realization. The meanings are the media, the resource, the condition for the unthinkable, for disturbance. Edwards conveniently or otherwise excludes this sentence from the above paragraph (p. 183): Through its distributive rules the pedagogic device is both the control on the "unthinkable" and the control on those who may think about it. (ibid. p. 158) These distributing strategies (this is Edwards, this is me) and positioning strategies (conveniently or otherwise excludes) effectively install Edwards in the correct quadrant of my diagram. Similar strategies are employed in respect of the Edwards other major misrepresentation: Edwards not only disconnects the core concepts but he also perpetuates the myth of the abstract theorist whose work both lacks an empirical base and lacks the power to describe that base adequately. (ibid. p. 157) An even more forceful strategy is represented in the reprinting in Bernsteins book of Edwards statement of mea culpa (originally published immediately following Bernsteins response in the Oxford Educational Review (Edwards, 1994). Edwards apology concludes: I am also persuaded to reconsider whether I have underused if not misused Bernsteins codes as a uniquely powerful heuristic in the study of pedagogic discourse. (Edwards, 1994, p. 184; Edwards in Bernstein, 1996, p. 168) Having thus recanted, Edwards is reinstated as a disciple. The third exploiter is perhaps particularly dangerous insofar as the authors, Richard Harker and Stephen May (1993) produce a comparison between Bernstein and Bourdieu, coming out very much in favour of the latter. Again, Bernstein published his response in the journal in which the original appeared (Bernstein, 1995) and reprinted it (with a minor alteration to the title and one less appendix) in his book (Bernstein, 1996). Again, I shall simply illustrate Bernsteins deployment of strategies which begins with an effective positioning of Harker and May as dilettanti within the academic field: Misrecognition takes a few lines but its exposure takes many. (ibid., p. 182) Later in the paper Bernstein introduces a quotation from the forward of a book edited by Bourdieu. The forward was written by Chamboredom and is reproduced by Bernstein in French and without translation. Bernsteins and his readers constructed bilingualism is clearly contrasted with the constructed monolingualism of Harker and May who can quote Bourdieu only in translation. In the (final) appendix to the paper/chapter, Bernstein lists what he describes as the most puzzling features of the representation of the code thesis (Bernstein, 1996; p. 199) again casting Harker and May as dilettanti he notes that: Clearly these puzzling features must be distinguished from serious, critical engagement without which there can be no development of a theory or of the intellectual field. (ibid.; p. 199) Bernstein proceeds to gloss each of these motivations together with what he describes as an optional field strategytime warpingand finishes his book thus: Now if we relate religious, epistemological and discursive positioning possibilities with temporal possibilities (time warping), we have a truly formidable set of combinations for generating and particularizing practices. We can render this slightly more formally. Religious, epistemological and discursive positioning are category relations, and so spatial and therefore subject to classificatory principles, whereas time warping is temporal, and so subject to framing. Thus we can begin to see how classification and framings regulate positioning and how modalities are a realization of field-constructed motivations. (ibid.; pp. 200-1) I shall refer again to this extract in the next section of this paper. Here, however, it is sufficient to say that Bernstein has succeeded in constituting the Harker and May paper as data in respect of his own message. In the absence of an apology from the authors there can, of course, be no rehabilitation. The heretics Heretics, of course, must speak their own message. I shall, therefore, confine myself to my own response to Bernsteins work. For many years now I have benefited and continue to benefit enormously from serious engagement with Bernsteins work, both published and, in the past, in terms of personal interactions. My own concern, however, is not the reproduction of this work, but to move from critical interaction with it and with the work of other key theoretical antecedents in the production of my own theoretical and empirical structures. I want here to give an indication of some of the crucial ways that key developments in my own work are related to Bernsteins ideas. There is no point in beating about the bush, so I shall begin with the two fundamental concepts of classification and framing. Specifically, I make extensive use of a concept of classification, but rarely refer to framing. Why is this? briefly, control establishes legitimate communications, and power establishes legitimate relations between categories. Thus, power constructs relations between, and control relations within given forms of interaction. (Bernstein, 1996; p. 19) Within Bernsteins work, the concepts are associated with opposing sets of terms as illustrated in Table 1. |
||||||||||||||||||||||
Classification and Framing |
||||||||||||||||||||||
For example: Whereas the recognition rule arises out of distinguishing between contexts, the realization rule arises out of the specific requirements within a context. We know that the principle of the classification governs relations between contexts, and that the principle of the framing regulates the transmission of appropriate practice within a context. (ibid.; p. 107) Framing is defined as follows:
Framing is about who controls what. What follows can be described as the internal logic of the pedagogic practice. Framing refers to the nature of the control over: Where framing is strong, the transmitter has explicit control over selection, sequence, pacing, criteria and the social base. Where framing is weak, the acquirer has more apparent control (I want to stress apparent) over the communication and its social base. Note that it is possible for framing valuesbe they strong or weakto vary with respect to the elements of the practice, so that, for example, you could have weak framing over pacing but strong framing over other aspects of the discourse. (ibid.; p. 27) Consider an example which is based on Mark Warschauers (1999) observation of an English non-fiction writing course at an American university. Warschauers interest was in the ways in which the teachers and students practices changed as the medium changed between face-to-face (f2f) and computer mediated communication (cmc). In particular, he found that the teacher tended to operate in a didactic lecturing mode in the f2f situation. CMC was described as more democratic, which is to say, the teacher intervened far less and with more open questions than in the f2f mode and it was the students rather than the teacher who apparently directed the discussions. Now in terms of the above definition, it would seem that the change in practice between the two modes constitutes a weakening of frame. Classification, however, has remained constant insofar as there has been no change in respect of the degree to which this class is to be distinguished from other classes. However, consider this statement by Bernstein: In the case of invisible pedagogic practice it is as if the pupil is the author of the practice and even the authority, whereas in the case of visible practices it clearly is the teacher who is author and authority. Further, classification would be strong in the case of visible forms but weak in the case of invisible forms. (Bernstein, 1996; p. 12) Now the cmc mode looks very much like an invisible pedagogy which here is described as exhibiting weak classification with no reference being made to framing. Elsewhere in Bernsteins book there is a virtual exclusion of the category framing in favour of classification; I noted only a single instance of it in chapter 3, for example. The source of the confusion, for me, resides in the fact that, as Bernstein himself notes (p. 19), power and control and so classification and framing operated at different levels of analysis. A crucial feature of power relations, for Bernstein, is the construction of boundaries or insulation, thus: The distinction I will make here is crucial and fundamental to the whole analysis. In this formulation, power and control are analytically distinguished and operate at different levels of analysis. Empirically, we shall find that they are embedded in each other. Power relations, in this perspective, create boundaries, legitimize boundaries, reproduce boundaries, between different categories of groups, gender, class, race, different categories of discourse, different catefories of agents. Thus, power always operates to produce dislocations, to produce punctuations in social space. [
] But I want to argue that the crucial space which creates the specializations of the categoryin this case the discourseis not internal to that discourse but is the space between that discourse and another. In other words, A can only be A if it can effectively insulate itself from B. In this sense, there is no A if there is no relationship between A and something else. The meaning of A is only understandable in relation to other categories in the set; in fact, to all the categories in the set. In other words, it is the insulation between the categories of discourse which maintains the principles of their social division of labour. In other words, it is silence which carries the message of power; it is the full stop between one category of discourse and another; it is the dislocation in the potential flow of discourse which is crucial to the specialization of any category. (Ibid.; pp. 19-20) This now finally brings me back to the Berlin wall. Now the wall is certainly implicated in the establishing of distinct political regimes. Implicated, but not imbricated. The substance of the wall is suitable for its purpose solely by virtue of its sharing of a predicate with that which it keeps apart. Specifically, the wall and the people on either side of it are mutually impervious. That is to say, in the constitution of a division of labourthe differentiating of political regimesthe function of the wall is to assert a sameness, not a difference. The same, incidentally, is true in respect of insulation. The plastic material surrounding domestic electrical cable shares the predicate of electrical conductance with bodies that it separates.[5] Again, the introduction of the boundary constitutes an assertion of sameness. To take a symbolic example, a full stopwritten or spokenagain asserts that the same kind of grammatical object is (or is potentially, in the case of a termination) to be found on either side. [6] To state the situation in terms of fundamental principles, a boundary is of necessity a moment in the precise region of a system in which it is constituted as a boundary. Classroom walls, then, create punctuations of space not curricular subjects. How do we move from a strongly classified physical space to a strongly classified curriculum? Not simply by labelling the doorssuch labels are merely addresses and addresses are like boundaries insofar as they assert participation in the same system. A strongly classified curriculum is not in any sense predicated upon a strongly classified physical space, although the former may well recruit the latter in sustaining its classification, just as an existing political system recruited the Berlin wall in sustaining its classification. Bernstein is correct only to a very limited extent in claiming that what is classified may be realised in different ways, specifically, in different interactional modes. The cmc classroom is plausibly one in which very strong classification is realised. Suppose, for example, that the teacher is completely silent, or lurks. S/he can, nevertheless, review every contribution made by the student which might then be graded according to highly specialised principles and pass lists subsequently published. The problem for the student, of course, would be gaining access to the principles; arguably, this is not a pedagogic situation, because there is no transmission. The teacher may transform the situation into a pedagogic one by employing either weakly or strongly framed strategies; open questioning or lecturing, say. However, open questioning can remain open only insofar as the principles to be transmitted are weakly specialised or, rather, only in respect of those regions or aspects of the discourse that are weakly specialised. The panopticon (Foucault, 1977) might be construed as the archetype of weak framing.[7] However, as with the teacher-lurker in the cmc environment, this can work only where the prisoner already possesses the principles of evaluation of their behaviour and that would not be a pedagogic situation because it would entail no transmission. Essentially the situation is as follows. Where that which is classified is the privileged content, or that which is to be transmitted, in a pedagogic situation, then the strength of framing of interactions must coincide with the strength of classification. Only where that which is classified is decoupled from this privileged content can classification and framing vary independently. An example of the latter would be, you can do anything you like so long as you do it in this room. Strong classification/weak framing, yes, but only because they do not refer to each other. The problem can be resolved once we recognise that it can be traced to Bernsteins original decoupling of space and time. Such decoupling is, of course, characteristic of various strands of structuralism and has been challenged in each of them; Derrida (1978) in respect of Saussure; Baudrillard (1993) in respect of Marx; Lacan (1977) in respect of Freud; Bourdieu (1977) in respect of Lévi-Strauss; and so forth. Bernstein and Piagetthe great educational structuralistshave remained substantially immune, to date (although see Dowling, 1998, in respect of Piaget). Essentially, a space-time decoupling can be sustained only to the extent that we ignore a shuffling between levels of analysis or (perhaps and) we keep our distance from the empirical. A consequence of the resolution of the problem is that of the four concepts, power, control, classification and framing, three are redundant. I propose to retain classification and, in the construction of my own language, dispense with the other three. Thus, I propose that activitiessay school mathematicsbe construed as strategic spaces whereby subjects are positioned and practices distributed. In particular, specialising strategies constitute practices which are strongly classified with respect to those of other activities. Pedagogic action must entail the transmission of these specialised practices. In order to achieve this, the transmitter must constitute a discourse that is accessible to the acquirer. This in turn is achieved when the transmitteras a subject of the activity in question, mathematicscasts a gaze beyond mathematics and recontextualises non-mathematical practice so that it conforms to the principles of specialised mathematical practice. Recontextualising is achieved by localising strategies, thus, the purchase of a loaf of bread in a supermarket becomes a local instance of specialised arithmetic. [8] The effect of these localising strategies is to constitute a region of school mathematical practice that is weakly classified with respect to the non-mathematical. This is the public domain which contrasts with the esoteric domain that comprises practices that are strongly classified with respect to the non-mathematical. [9] My concept of recontextualisation is also a heresy in respect of Bernsteins work. Bernsteins use of the term refers to the creation of imaginary discourses from real discourses according to the recontextualising principle that is pedagogic discourse via the embedding of an instructional discourse in a regulative discourse. Instructional discourse refers to specialised skills and regulative discourse to a moral order. By way of examples, Bernstein offers the recontextualising of carpentrya real discourseas woodworkan imaginary discourse and the recontextualising of university physics as school physics. My concern is that Bernsteins theorising is constituting an unnecessary priority and not a little confusion. In order to demonstrate this, I shall need to work towards Bernsteins higher level concept, the pedagogic device. I will begin with an extract from Class, Codes and Control volume 4. It is of course obvious that all pedagogic discourse creates a moral regulation of the social relations of transmission/acquisition, that is, rules of order, relation, and identity; and that such a moral order is prior to, and a condition for, the transmission of competences. This moral order is in turn subject to a recontextualizing principle, and thus this order is a signifier for something other than itself. (Bernstein, 1991; p. 184) The mode of expression has been modified in the revised version of this chapter (see Bernstein, 1996, c. 3)it is no longer quite so universally obvious, apparently. The theoretical formulation is retained, however, and the regulative (moral) discourse remains the dominant discourse (Bernstein, 1996; p. 46) vis a vis the discourse concerning the transmission of competences (the instructional discourse). However, in the 1996 version, the distinction between regulative and instructional discourse is analytic or, perhaps, ideological: In my opinion, there is only one discourse, not two, because the secret voice of [the pedagogic] device is to disguise the fact that there is only one. Most researchers are continually studying the two, or thinking as if there are two: as if education is about values on the one hand, and about competence on the other. In my view there are not two discourses, there is only one. (Bernstein, 1996; p. 46) There is only one, yet one of them is dominant. A little further on:
pedagogic discourse is a recontextualizing principle. Pedagogic discourse is constructed by a recontextualizing principle which selectively appropriates, relocates, refocuses and relates other discourses to constitute its own order. In this sense, pedagogic discourse can never be identified with any of the discourses it has recontextualized. (ibid.; pp. 47-8) The apparent confusion here is, so far as I can determine, the result of a failure by Bernstein to use key terms consistently and to constitute neologisms when and only when they are needed. Bernstein is clearer when providing an example.
the authors of textbooks in physics are rarely physicists who are practising in the field of the production of physics; they are working in the field of recontextualization. (ibid.; pp. 48-9) Bernstein may well be correct in his claim that school physics textbook authors are not generally productive phycisists. However, this rather misses the point. The authors of university physics textbooks generally are productive physicists, yet there are many important differences between university textbooks and, say, research papers (see Myers, 1992, also Dowling, 1998). The downplaying of the relevance of the logic of the discourse of physics in its recontextualised form is also open to some challenge. In an associated field, for example, the development of the modern school mathematics in the nineteen fifties and sixties was heavily influenced by the Bourbakiist principle of mother structures (see Dowling, 1989, Moon, 1986). It is also questionable whether the field of production is the only or even the dominant object of the gazes of recontextualising agents. The nature of integral calculus in advanced level mathematics certainly attests to this. Essentially, Bernstein is making empirical claims and providing quasi-empirical illustrations in order to bolster his theoretical apparatus. The productivity of the more esoteric regions of this apparatus is difficult to imagine. In an earlier formulation, the instrumental and expressive orders constituted schemes through which the school might be and indeed was analysed as I have indicated in the comments relating to King.[10] Now there is only one discourse. Jean Lave and Etienne Wenger agree that school physics is very different from university physics. They suggest that the decoupling may be even greater than Bernstein seems to imply: in most schools there is a group of students engaged over a substantial period of time in learning physics. What community of practice is in the process of reproduction? Possibly the students participate only in the reproduction of the high school itself. (Lave & Wenger, 1991, p. 99) In my conception the school as a site is to be conceived as a moment of a sociocultural system (Baudrillard, not Parsons). In terms of interaction, all such sites are characterised by a specific form of articulation of two modes of social activity. Pedagogic activity entails a transmitter, and acquirer, and a privileged content in respect of which the principles of evaluation of texts or performances resides with the transmitter. In an exchange activity the principles of evaluation are located with the acquirer. Strongly classified content is transmitted under pedagogic relations; weakly classified content is transmitted under exchange relations. The distribution of these relations constitutes differentiation within the school. I have now made tacit reference to all three dimensions of Bernsteins pedagogic device: distribution, recontextualisation, and evaluation. Bernsteins pedagogic devicepresumably, the something other than itself for which pedagogic discourse is a signifieris a heretical recontextualising of Chomskys language acquisition device with Bernstein explicitly adopting a Hallidayan rather than a Chomskian methodology. Bernstein argues: Both the language device and the pedagogic device become sites for appropriation, conflict and control. At the same time, there is a crucial difference between the two devices. In the case of the pedagogic device, but not in the case of the language device, it is possible to have an outcome, a form of communication which can subvert the fundamental rules of the device. (Bernstein, 1996, p. 42) But, of course, these devices cannot become sites for any such thing. They are not, in fact, sites at all because they are not, ultimately, empirically operationalisable. The pedagogic device is a very high level theoretical object and we must descend through multiple layers of theory before we ever get to something that we might validly refer to an empirical text. The pedagogic device is a part of Bernsteins internal language: Briefly, a language of description is a translation device whereby one language is transformed into another. We can distinguish between internal and external languages of description. The internal language of description refers to the syntax whereby a conceptual language is created. The external language of description refers to the syntax whereby the internal language can describe something other than itself. (Bernstein, 1996; pp. 135-6) Bernsteins own work has a strong tendency to reside in the internal. It is left to his disciples to generate external languages. By and large, these tend to be very thin, commonly making reference to boundaries and insulation and so forth which, as I have argued above, entail serious theoretical problems. My formulation of my own general methodologywhich I refer to as constructive description is illustrated in Figure 2. I shall not give any extended discussion of this diagram here (but see Dowling 1998, 1999). It is important to note, however, that the principal theoretical and empirical achievementsuch as it isof my work takes place in the area signified by the box corresponding to Bernsteins external language. That is, at the point of interface between the theoretical and the empirical. Bernstein seems to want to produce a theoretical system that is a model of what might metaphorically be described as the consciousness of society. My own project is far less ambitious. I am simply trying to manufacture a machine that will help me to organise what I see. In order to move between levels of analysissay between the analysis of a conversation and the analysis of school practices (move 1) and the analysis of state policy (move 2), and so forth, I simply reapply the same conceptual framework, generating indicators that are appropriate to the new level. The method has, in this respect, a fractal quality. Recontextualisation in my language, then, is far more generalisable than it would appear to be in Bernsteins. I define it as the subordination of the practices of one activity to the principles of another. It is precisely the empirical analysis of the productivity of recontextualisation that enables the constructive description of the recontextualising activity. |
||||||||||||||||||||||
Schema for the Constructive Description |
||||||||||||||||||||||
The categories, classification and framing also exhibit this fractal quality. Their disadvantage lies, as I have argued, in the fact that they do not themselves occupy the same level of analysis. A good deal of Bernsteins theory (and here he is certainly not alone) is fixed in terms of its referent level. It may be that this is associated with his preference, following Halliday, for network analysis. This is an approach that fixes levels of analysis in relation to each other as one moves between levels of the network. I would describe a network as an analysis that has been terminated at a stage prior to the full development of theory. Bernstein has similar reservations about ideal types:
Classically the ideal type is constructed by assembling in a model a number of features abstracted from a phenomenon in such a way as to provide a means of identifying the presence or absence of the phenomenon, and a means of identifying the 'workings' of the phenomenon from an analysis of the assembly of its features. Ideal types constructed in this way cannot generate other than themselves. They are not constructed by a principle which generates sets of relations of which any one form may be only one of the forms the principle may regulate. (ibid.; p. 126-7) My feeling is that it is inappropriate to crystallise a method in this way. I explicitly describe my own approach as employing ideal types. However, my approach is to make a group of ideal types conceptually coherent to the point that they participate in the same theoretical system. Pedagogic and exchange relations constitute a case in point: they are defined in relation to each other in terms of the variable, location of the principles of evaluation. The application of an empirically driven network analysis does not encourage theorising to this level; the development of a theoretically driven network does not encourage empirical operationalisation. A vertical discourse takes the form of a coherent, explicit, systematically principled structure, hierarchically organized, or it takes the form of a series of specialized languages with specialized modes of interrogation and specialized criteria for the production of texts. (ibid.; p. 171) |
||||||||||||||||||||||
Bernsteins Discursive Map (Source: Bernstein, 1996; p. 175) |
||||||||||||||||||||||
The natural sciences are offered as characterised by the former mode (hierarchical knowledge structure) and the humanities and social sciences by the latter (horizontal knowledge structures). Now my question is, where does the essential quality of the knowledge reside? Is it in the day-to-day working practices of practitioners, or in the structure of learned journals, in the lexicon of specialised terms, in the activities of research funding agencies, in models of apprenticeship of new practitioners? I could continue. Having some experience of higher education in both the natural and social sciences, my suspicion is that any discipline will exhibit variations in terms of horizontality and hierarchising as we shift attention between these and other contexts. In any event, both Bernsteins original claim and my suspicion raise empirical questions that remain to be addressed. Nevertheless, the kind of distinction that Bernstein is making is potentially productive. In my own work I have drawn on this and on a whole set of other attempts at establishing corresponding oppositions, including Bernsteins own restricted/elaborated codes (see Table 2) in formulating the distinction between two strategic modes. Empirical texts can be measured in terms of the extent to which they tend to realise the principles of an activity in discursive form, which is to say, to render them context independent. Texts which exhibit this feature are said to (re)produce a high discursive saturation practice (DS+). On the other hand, texts which tend to render the principles in context dependent form are said to (re)produce a low discursive saturation practice. Incorporating this variable in the system that I have begun to develop in this paper I produce the strategic space shown in Figure 4. The distinction between specialising and generalising and between localising and articulating is that the former element in each pair operates to delimit the range of application of the practice, whilst the latter extends it. Again, I do not propose to elaborate further on this construction, other than to raise the claim that it facilitates both theoretical development and the analysis of empirical texts. In particular, differentiation within and between educational settings can productively be described in terms of the apparent mislocation of a practice. Thus, a great deal of mathematical practice distributed to lower ability students is constituted in terms of localising and articulating strategies within the context of exchange relations. See Dowling, in press, for some further discussion of a slightly earlier formulation of this strategic space and its relation to other moments of my language of description together with some illustrative textual analysis. |
||||||||||||||||||||||
The Dual Modality of Practice [11] |
||||||||||||||||||||||
Strategic Space |
||||||||||||||||||||||
I do not intend to install a separate concluding section to this paper, because in doing so I would not move out of my heretical position; the division would be redundant. I have introduced four modes of response to Bernsteins work. The vulgarisers will congregate as an inevitable excrescence on the surface of any work that is at once high profile. Such work which is at the same time complex and difficultand Bernsteins is most definitely all threewill also attract exploiters. These authors may be inspired positively or negatively by elements of the work, but foreground their own projects at the expense of allowing Bernsteins voice to speak to them too loudly. This, of course, is an entirely acceptable course of action. However, the profound value of the work itself is only fully realised in the activities of the disciples and the heretics. As an energetic heretic, my engagement with Bernstein is fundamental and deliberately schismatic. Bernsteins response to such heresy may take any or all of a number of forms. He may be inclined to attempt to establish me as an exploiter. So far, he has limited himself to claiming me as a disciple. As well as an inclusion in his acknowledgements (for which I am grateful and flattered) I am recruited by the following remark (for which I am less so): Dowling (following Bernstein, 1981, 1986, 1995) constructed a language of description for the translation of maths textbook[s] into sociological discourse. (ibid.; p. 142) There is absolutely no doubt in my mind that my own work could not have been achieved without his application of stunningly original strategies of localisation, articulation, specialising and generalising. As Donna Haraway (1991) has pointed out blasphemy is not apostasy and the same is clearly true of heresy. Excommunicated or not, I remain a (heretical) bernsteinian. Notes 1. I do not propose to derive indicators for the quantification of either dimension; the reference to the interval level is an analogy only. 2. No contemporary fieldnotes being available, I am reconstructing the dialogue as best I can on the basis of unaided memory. 3. A finding which I cannot resist associating with Beckers famous description of the careers of marijuana users. 4. A distinction that, of course, predates Bernstein and so whilst sharpened by, cannot be interpreted as simply the product of his theorising. back 5. In this case, the insulation must have a low value of conductance in order to separate two bodies having high conductance. In this sense, insulation is a negative kind of wall. 6. It would seem that this is a general rule for punctuation marks. Questions marks, for example, that appear to stand in breach of the rule are not, qua question marks, boundaries. That which follows a question mark may or may not be a question. What is asserted, however, is that it will be another sentence. 7. Or, in an schooling context, Samuel Wilderspins use of cherry trees in the playground (see Hunter, 1994; Dowling, 1998). 8. In another context, the purchase of a loaf of bread might become the localised instance of specialised domestic science and would be recontextualised to quite different effect. 9. In Dowling (1998 and elsewhere) I measure strength of classification in respect of content and expression separately, thus generating a two dimensional space. The esoteric and public domains refer to those regions for which content and expression are both strong or weak, respectively. The other two possibilities give rise to the descriptive and expressive domains. 10. See also Power et al (1998). 11. The table refers to the following work: Bernstein (1977); Bourdieu (1977, 1990); Eco (1976, regarding Lotman); Foucault (1980); Freud (1973); Lévi-Strauss (1972); Luria (1976, and regarding Lévy-Bruhl); Piaget (1995); Sohn-Rethel (1973, 1975, 1978); Vygotsky (1978, 1986); Walkerdine (1982). References BAUDRILLARD, J. (1993). Symbolic Exchange and Death. London: Sage. BERNSTEIN, B. (1971). Class, Codes and Control Volume 1: theoretical studies towards a sociology of language. London: RKP. BERNSTEIN, B. (1977). Class, Codes and Control Volume 3: towards a theory of educational transmissions. second edition. London: RKP. BERNSTEIN, B. (1990). Class, Codes and Control volume 4. London: RKP. BERNSTEIN, B. (1994). Edwards and his language codes: response to A.D. Edwards, language codes and classroom practice. Oxford Review of Education. 20. 2. pp 173-182. BERNSTEIN, B. (1995). Code theory and its positioning: a case study in misrecognition. British Journal of Sociology of Education. 16(2), pp 3-19. BERNSTEIN, B. (1996). Pedagogy, Symbolic Control and Identity: theory, research critique. London: Taylor & Francis. BOURDIEU, P. (1977). Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge: CUP. BOURDIEU, P. (1990). The Logic of Practice. Cambridge: Polity. CENTRAL ADVISORY COUNCIL FOR EDUCATION. (1963). Children and Their Primary Schools. London: HMSO. DANIELS, H. (1988). An enquiry into different forms of special school organization. Collected Original Resources in Education. 12(2), DANIELS, H. (1995). Pedagogic practices, tacit knowledge and discursive discrimination: Bernstein and post-Vygotskian research. British Journal of Sociology of Education. 16(2), pp. 517-532. DERRIDA, J. (1978). Writing and Difference. London: RKP. DOWLING, P.C. (in press). School Mathematics in late modernity: Beyond myths and fragmentation in Atweh, B. (Ed). Socio-Cultural Aspects of Mathematics Education: An International Research Perspective. Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Earlbaum. DOWLING, P.C. (1989). The Contextualising of Mathematics: towards a theoretical map. In Collected Original Resources in Education. 13, 2. Also in Harris, M. (Ed). (1990) School, Mathematics and Work, Basingstoke: Falmer. DOWLING, P.C. (1998). The Sociology of Mathematics Education: Mathematical Myths/Pedagogic Texts. London: Falmer Press. DOWLING, P.C. (1999) Interrogating Education: Texts, Social Activity and Constructive Description. Plenary presentation at Centro de Investigação em Educação da Faculdade de Ciências da Universidade de Lisboa, April 1999. http://www.ioe.ac.uk/ccs/dowling/lisbon1999. ECO, U. (1976). A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. EDWARDS, A. D. (1987). Language codes and classroom practice. Oxford Review of Education. 13(2), pp. 237-247. EDWARDS, A. D. (1994) A reply to Basil Bernstein. Oxford Review of Education. 20(2), pp. 183-184. FOUCAULT, M. (1977). Discipline and Punish: the birth of the prison. London: Penguin. FOUCAULT, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge. Brighton: Harvester. FREUD, S. (1973). New Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis. London: Penguin. HARAWAY, D. J. (1991). A Cyborg Manifesto: science, technology, and socialist-feminism in the late twentieth century. In D. J. Haraway (Ed.), Simians, Cyborgs and Women: the reinvention of nature . London: Free Association Books. HARKER, R. & MAY, S. (1993). Code and Habitus: comparing the accounts of Bernstein and Bourdieu. British Journal of Sociology of Education. 14(2), pp. 169-178. HUNTER, I. (1994). Rethinking the School: subjectivity, bureaucracy, criticism. St Leonards: Allen & Unwin. KING, R. (1976). Bernsteins sociology of the schoolsome propositions tested. British Journal of Sociology. 27(2), pp. 430-443. KING, R. (1981). Bernsteins sociology of the schoola futher testing. British Journal of Sociology. 32(2), pp. 259-265. LACAN, J. (1977). Écrits. London: Tavistock. LAVE, J., & WENGER, E. (1991). Situated Learning: Legitimate Peripheral Participation. Cambridge: CUP. LÉVI-STRAUSS, C. (1972). The Savage Mind (La Pensée Sauvage). London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson. LURIA, A. R. (1976). Cognitive Development: its cultural and social foundations. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. MOON, B. (1986). The 'New Maths' Controversy: an international story. Lewes: Falmer. MORAIS, A.M. & ANTUNES, H. (1994). Students' differential text production in the regulative context of the classroom. British Journal of Sociology of Education. 15(2), pp. 243-263. MORAIS, A.M., NEVE, I.P. & FONTINHAS, F. (1992). Recognition and realisation rules in acquiring school science: the contribution of pedagogy and social background of students. British Journal of Sociology of Education. 13(2), pp. 247-270. MORAIS, A.M., NEVE, I.P. & FONTINHAS, F. (1999). Is there any change in science educational reforms? A sociological study of theories of instruction. British Journal of Sociology of Education. 20(2), pp. 37-54. MYERS, G. (1992). Textbooks and the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge. English for Specific Purposes. 11(1), pp. 3-17. PIAGET, J. (1995). Sociological Studies. London: RKP. POWER, S., WHITTY, G., EDWARDS, T. & WIGFALL, V. (1998). Schools, families and academically able students: contrasting modes of involvement in secondary education. British Journal of Sociology of Education. 19(2), pp. 157-176. SOHN-RETHEL, A. (1973). Intellectual and Manual Labour. Radical Philosophy. 6, pp. 30-7. SOHN-RETHEL, A. (1975). Science as Alienated Consciousness. Radical Science Journal, 2/3, pp. 63-101. SOHN-RETHEl, A. (1978). Intellectual and Manual Labour: a critique of epistemology. London: MacMillan. TYLER, W. (1988). School Organisation: A sociological perspective. London: Croom Helm. VYGOTSKY, L. S. (1978). Mind in Society: the development of higher psychological processes. Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press. VYGOTSKY, L. S. (1986). Thought and Language. Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press. WALKERDINE, V. (1982). From Context to Text: a psychosemiotic approach to abstract thought. In M. Beveridge (Ed.), Children Thinking Through Language, . London: Arnold. WARSCHAUER, M. (1999). Electronic Literacies: language, culture and power in online education. Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence erlbaum Associates. |